logo

57 pages 1 hour read

Martin Heidegger

Being And Time

Martin HeideggerNonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 1927

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Division 1, Chapter 3

Division 1: “Preparatory Fundamental Analysis of Dasein”

Division 1, Chapter 3, Sections 14-15 Summary

In the previous chapters of Division 1, Heidegger looked at the meaning of Dasein’s “being-in-the world.” In preliminary fashion, he gave an account of our “being-in” that rejected the idea of a “bare perceptual cognition” (95). Instead, our primary mode of world-relation, and the basis for our intimacy with the world, was found to be a practical one, seen to reside in a “concern which manipulates things and puts them to use” (95). However, this “practical engagement” notion remained abstract. In this chapter, Heidegger aims to describe in more concrete terms what this practical relation involves and what it signifies philosophically.

As he explains, in our pragmatic dealings with the world, we do not first encounter “things.” Rather we find what Heidegger calls “equipment” ready to use, “ready-to-hand.” This is not to be thought of in terms of distinct “items of equipment,” such as knives, pans, or chopping boards. On the contrary: “To the Being of any equipment there always belongs a totality of equipment, in which it can be this equipment that it is” (97). In other words, with the ready-to-hand, what we primarily encounter is a network of interconnected relations, or a matrix, of equipment. For example, we discover the knife, and it is grasped as a knife, in its relation to the chopping board, the work surface, and the vegetables to be cut. Similarly, we deal with the knife, and it gains its meaning, in its relation to the context of the more general workspace, in this instance of the kitchen.

Moreover, such relations are not arbitrary or self-enclosed. They themselves gain their meaning, and are organized in relation to, the specific goal of the broader task at hand. The kitchen equipment complex, for instance, comes to life only via the implicitly understood aim of preparing a meal. This implies, in turn, an awareness of other Dasein. When we are cooking, for example, we never do so for its’ own sake. We do so with a concern for the Dasein who will eat the meal, even if this other Dasein is us. So, too, the tailor must make clothes cut to measure, with the proportions of other Dasein in mind. Such considerations are not a reflective after-thought: They are not something to be considered merely once the task is finished and we presently have to serve the other. Instead, they co-constitute the very nature of the assignment and the way we realize the equipment related to it. They do so as something to be continually and implicitly taken into account in our work.

Division 1, Chapter 3, Sections 16-24 Summary

There is a question that Heidegger must address following from the discussion in the previous section. While there is an implicit type of understanding involved in our engagement with equipment, and such activity is not unconscious or mechanical, our very absorption in it seems to preclude explicit awareness. As Heidegger says, the ready-to-hand relations of equipment, “must, as it were, withdraw in order to be ready-to-hand quite authentically” (99). That is, a condition of using equipment skillfully is that the character of the equipment becomes inconspicuous. For example, to effectively use a computer, it is necessary that we are not explicitly and consciously aware of how to type when doing so. The specific activity of typing, the skill and equipment it involves, must rather remain in the background if we are to proficiently construct sentences.

This presents the problem of how Dasein in general, and Heidegger in particular, gains awareness of all this. How, given the inconspicuousness of the ready-to-hand, is Dasein to gain the kind of explicit awareness required for making philosophical claims about it? Heidegger’s answer in section 16 is elegant. It is in the breakdown of equipment that this is achieved. As he argues, “when an assignment has been disturbed—when something is unusable for some purpose—then the assignment becomes explicit” (105). In other words, the equipment complex and its relations become suddenly conspicuous when our skillful absorption in the task is interrupted.

Consider again the computer. When it is operating smoothly, and we in harmony with it, we notice fully neither the lettered keys nor the way we manipulate them in order to write. When a key breaks, however, we are jolted into a multifaceted awareness of the broken letter, the keyboard, and the task itself. Indeed, with this breakdown, Heidegger argues, not just the specific piece of equipment but the totality of relations underscoring out use of it is brought to light. For instance, we become aware of the computer as an obtrusive object resisting us. Also brought into focus is the study space in which the computer resides, and ourselves as someone being frustrated by it. On top of this, we are suddenly reminded why it is important that we finish the essay, and of the teacher we will let down if it is late. In short, brought to the foreground is a world of relations that constituted our dealing with the equipment.

Division 1, Chapter 3 Analysis

The discussion of the “ready-to-hand” in Chapter 3 is one of the most intuitive, and accessible, elements of Being and Time. After all, we all have encounters with types of equipment every day, and Heidegger’s phenomenology allows us to see these habitual, but often unconsidered, experiences in a new light. However, for Heidegger, such insight is not an end-in-itself. He is pursuing a project of phenomenological ontology. As such, his goal is not just to give phenomenological descriptions, but to draw ontological conclusions in connection with them. Specifically, he is looking with phenomenology to problematize the “ontology of presence” that dominates our thinking about the world. Chapter 3 does this in a variety of ways.

For one thing, it gives concrete form to an alternative way of apprehending the world that does not involve seeing a present-at-hand object. As Heidegger says, “No matter how sharply we just look at the ‘outward appearance’ of Things in whatever form this takes, we cannot discover anything ready-to hand” (98). That is, the “ready-to-hand” cannot be grasped by a detached subject just staring at it. It can be understood only in our immersed dealings with it. To use Heidegger’s example, we only discover the hammer, properly speaking, in the activity of hammering. This has ontological implications for the nature of the ready-to-hand, for it is constituted then, in its being, by its relations. It is its relations, and in a way that means it can never be ontologically self-sufficient or self-identical.

We have already touched on the nature of these relations in connection with the “equipment complex” and other Dasein; similarly, the ready-to-hand is also its relation to the specific Dasein using it. Conversely, Dasein is a relation to the ready-to-hand in that instance. When we are cooking, for example, the sense of a distinct self and distinct objects recedes. Instead, we have an emerging unity between self and world, constituted by our absorption in the task. This equates to what Heidegger calls “the public world” (100). The ready-to-hand is not merely related to the specific equipment of its task; it is also ontologically connected, albeit in a more indistinct way, to the broader world that provides the context for the task taking place. For instance, the activity of producing a tire makes sense only in a world where there are cars, roads, and a need for fast transportation. The activity of tire-making must implicitly exist as a relation to all of this.

The challenge to the ontology of presence in Chapter 3 does not end there. In the manner that the ready-to-hand is explicitly revealed, important indications about the nature of non-being are also given. In the breakdown of equipment, which discloses the otherwise inconspicuous relations of the ready-to-hand, important departures from “present” ways of thinking are found. This is a question of what is disclosed, for on initial appearances it seems that Heidegger has a problem. If equipment as a set of relations exists in our absorbed use of it, then the very interruption making this explicit seems to destroy its character as equipment. In other words, Heidegger appears to be caught on the horns of a dilemma. On the one hand, we can have an awareness of the ready-to-hand as relational, but this must remain implicit. On the other hand, there is a break in the task, which makes the “equipment” explicit but as now out of joint with the fluid relations that defined it. It is then made explicitly available to understanding, but it is so now only as a set of present-at-hand objects.

Closer inspection, though, reveals that something more subtle is going on. As Heidegger says about the ready-to-hand, when it breaks down, “It does not vanish simply, but takes its farewell, as it were, in the conspicuousness of the unusable” (104). What this means is that it is in fact possible to explicitly grasp equipment after our absorption in it has ended, but what we apprehend is not the re-emergence of the present-at-hand. Nor is there a present-at-hand awareness of equipment. This would amount to an “observing” of a set of equipment relations as if it were a distinct object. Rather, what we apprehend is the disappearance of something. We apprehend the set of equipment relations precisely in its vanishing. That is, we grasp it in and through its sudden absence in relation to ourselves. It is like, by way of analogy, the apprehension of a friend’s death. This is not accomplished by viewing a present-at-hand corpse, nor by looking at photographs or reminiscing. Instead, their death, and their relation to you, is revealed by noticing a bench on which they used to sit. They are revealed precisely through and as their absence from that which used to indicate them.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
Unlock IconUnlock all 57 pages of this Study Guide

Plus, gain access to 8,800+ more expert-written Study Guides.

Including features:

+ Mobile App
+ Printable PDF
+ Literary AI Tools