57 pages • 1 hour read
Martin HeideggerA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Summary
Chapter Summaries & Analyses
Key Figures
Themes
Index of Terms
Important Quotes
Essay Topics
Tools
A discussion of the “who” of Dasein in the last chapter led Heidegger to an account of our being-with-others as constitutive of this. It also led to a discussion of a totally absorbed mode of this being-with, where our distinct self is lost in the generality and obscurity of the “they.” Such lostness is the ordinary and initial state of everyday Dasein. As such, to grasp our being-in-the-world properly, and its possibilities for authentic and inauthentic being, it is necessary to examine the nature of this “they” more closely. Heidegger does this in Chapter 5 by first looking at two phenomena that have up to now been kept in parentheses. These are moods and discourse. He does this because both are constituting modes of understanding, related modes of how the world is disclosed to us. As we saw in the last chapter, understanding, or its absence, is key to the nature of the they. In short, it is necessary to analyze moods and discourse to understand understanding, since through this we can then truly grasp the “they.” It is necessary as well so as to understand how we are able to understand the they in the first place, and it can simultaneously help reveal what stops us from doing so.
Heidegger begins with moods. His first claim is that moods, as opposed to specific emotions, are always present for us. Even when we say that we are not feeling anything in particular, this is a mood of apathy and indifference, or tranquility. It is only their relative inconspicuousness, and certain theoretical pre-conceptions, that might confuse us on this point. Relatedly, moods are revealing of the world in a way in which reflection is not. As Heidegger says, “Pure beholding, even if it were to penetrate to the innermost core of the Being of something present-at-hand, could never discover anything like that which is threatening” (177). In other words, theoretical reflection can never directly disclose the nature of what Heidegger calls our “care” in the world. This intimate involvement with the world, our projects, dealings, and coping, is revealed only through the felt concern constitutive of a mood.
He highlights this point by looking at a determinate mood—in this case, fear. When we are afraid, we are afraid for ourselves, but as Heidegger says, “Only an entity for which in its Being this very Being is an issue, can be afraid” (180). What we fear, then, is not pain, nor is it an instinctual fear of death; it is fear of losing our relation to the world. In this way, fear discloses our concerned involvement with the world, our being-in-the-world.
Just as mood always reveals, and is, a type of understanding, so, too, “Understanding always has its mood” (182). Understanding is not detached but occurs within the context of a mood and a concern. What this is, further, is disclosed when we again consider our practical dealings with the world. We have a pre-theoretical understanding of something when we are engaged with it skillfully, when we “manage”. This kind of skilled understanding in projects is not present-at-hand. On the contrary, what is revealed there is that Dasein “is not yet” but “is what it becomes” (186). Dasein is its possibilities in relation to the involved project to be completed. States-of-mind, or moods, allow us to “see” the possibilities of the world that we are in a deeper way.
This type of practical understanding leads to what Heidegger calls “interpretation.” From such interpretation, and the meaningful understanding that comes with it, we get various forms of expression. That is, Dasein seeks to express and articulate its understanding of the world to, and in relation to, others. It seeks to communicate, and this communication becomes, after mere assertion, “discourse.” In discourse there is saying and speaking but also, importantly, hearing. This hearing depends in turn upon language, which has its own mood through modulation, tone of voice, and tempo.
Heidegger stresses as well that we hear, and have language, in relation to our concern with the world. As such, just as we hear the car in the street, not a collection of sounds, in discourse we first “hear” the meaning and intention of the speaker. This is prior to any specific noises they make or linguistic formulations they employ. In other words, we do not first hear words that then need interpreting. We rather immediately grasp some more basic concern between the speaker and ourselves. This could be a warning, a demand, a plea, a welcome. Indeed, as Heidegger points out, it is possible to communicate without using words at all. In this way, an understanding of the practical, concerned “use” of language must come before logic and grammar in the study of discourse.
Moods and understanding are typically seen to be opposed. In standard philosophy and common sense, “objective” understanding is held to be distinct from the former. “Dispassionate” reflective reason and empirical fact, so it goes, are the way to truth, and emotions are only distorting to it. Further, where they do feature, their role is small. It might be granted that emotions give us access to an “inner” domain of the subjective, but this point should remain within strict limits. Indeed, even where more considered accounts of the relation emerge, they remain hostage to this basic concept. That is, they tend to see emotion as a sort of assistant to reason, regarding it either as a useful early warning system, or as a supplementary means of verification.
Heidegger rejects almost all of this, which does not mean, as he says, “attempting to surrender science ontically to ‘feeling’” (177). He is not engaged in a romantic project of valorizing inner, subjective experience and emotion over “reason.” Rather, his goal is to re-orient what we mean by moods in the first place and he aims to dissolve, rather than invert, the reason-emotion dichotomy. A criticism of the subject-object view, and the ontology of presence underlying it, plays a part in how he does this. As such, he begins by outlining more precisely the way moods are standardly conceived, or what can be described as the “colouring” view. According to this view, as Heidegger says, a mood is “an inner condition which then reaches forth in an enigmatical way and puts it marks on Things and persons” (176). The world is then essentially still composed of present-at-hand objects and subjects staring out at them. Emotions and moods, however, may then add a subjective “gloss” to those objects. For example, if we are in a good mood, the garden may impress us as “pleasant,” whereas in a bad mood, it strikes us as dull or lackluster.
There are several problems with this view for Heidegger. Aside from the means by which this “colouring” or “projection” occurs being obscure, it seems to violate the phenomenology in question. That is, this view does not describe our actual experience of moods and the world but is rather a post-hoc way of reconciling emotions with the unshakeable assumption that the world is composed of subjects and objects. Indeed, it is a classic example of how reified theory and ontology can distort interpretation of a phenomenon. On the other hand, holding in check the subject-object prejudice, and the ideal of presence, Heidegger can describe the nature of emotions more faithfully.
When we do this, we discover that moods are not some “internal,” and prior, state to be projected onto things. As Heidegger says, “The mood has already disclosed, in every case, Being-in-the-world as a whole, and makes it possible first of all to direct one-self towards something” (176). What this means is that moods do not exist first in, or emerge from, a domain of the subjective to be later added to the world. They are rather already always co-constituting of it. As the expression of our essential concerns and projects, they are what emerges with and through the world as a complex of equipment, involvements, and situations. They are that which, as an expression of our care, allows any orientation towards the world to take place at all. Conversely, the world and its concerns allow the mood to exist.
In this way, we can see how moods allow for understanding. If our primary relation to the world is in terms of equipment and concerned involvement, rather than detached observation, moods can disclose this in a unique fashion. Further, there is a specific mood that is especially revealing for Heidegger. In the previous discussion on the nature of the “they,” it was said that to simultaneously understand and escape our absorption in the familiar public world, a disruption or interruption of it was needed. A very provisional outline of what this involves was then given. This alluded to the occurrence of something uncanny in the social world. Now, however, Heidegger explains more exactly what this awareness is based on. It is not, as should be obvious, something that one can reason oneself into, nor is it something that one can voluntarily and consciously seek out. Rather it emerges on the basis of a particular mood. It emerges through “anxiety.” This emotion, in which we become aware of the “uncanniness” (234), the unfamiliar, or the “not-at-home” (234) of the they-world, can precipitate the latter’s breakdown. A full analysis of this comes in Heidegger’s discussion of death in Division 2 of the text.
Plus, gain access to 8,800+ more expert-written Study Guides.
Including features: