logo

58 pages 1 hour read

Thomas More

Utopia

Thomas MoreFiction | Novel | Adult | Published in 1516

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more. For select classroom titles, we also provide Teaching Guides with discussion and quiz questions to prompt student engagement.

Themes

The Origins of Social Problems and Their Solutions

One of the central and unifying themes of Utopia is the question of how and why social problems arise. Connected to this is the issue of how such social problems (e.g., poverty, crime, political corruption) might be effectively addressed. What sort of political and legal apparatuses should be used to solve such problems? Should we treat social problems as manageable but unavoidable symptoms of human nature? Or, recognizing that these problems arise from the social conditions in which individuals live, should we attempt to alter those conditions such that the problems disappear?

More’s novel broaches this theme in different ways. Throughout the dialogues that comprise Book 1, the characters present a range of perspectives on these questions and related issues. The English lawyer with whom Raphael dines in Book 1 exhibits a lack of reflection about these issues; he cannot understand why capital punishment is not an effective deterrent to theft because he has not even attempted to understand why people steal. In allowing the lawyer to appear naïve or obtuse with respect to these questions, More encourages the reader to reflect upon this theme even before Raphael raises the issue just a few lines later (22).

According to Raphael, capital punishment does not deter theft for a simple reason: Economic trends, driven by a greedy desire to maximize profits on the part of landowners, have displaced large numbers of agricultural workers who have no other marketable skills. Between the choice of starving and theft, they choose theft (22). No one is naturally greedy except perhaps from a prideful desire to exalt themselves above others by ostentatious displays of wealth. In other words, Raphael sees social problems—including expressions of human vice—as facilitated by systematic forces. Theft is not a function of innate evil or disobedience but of broader political and economic forces. To do real justice, the causes of poverty and hunger must be rooted out. Raphael offers us a systematic approach to diagnosing social problems. By the same token, he suggests that solving these problems in a just fashion requires radical change: Sweeping structural changes must be instituted to eliminate their root causes. For Raphael this means eliminating private property, which he believes is the root of all these social evils.

More suggests that social problems arise due to inherent and immutable qualities of the human species (42). Because of this, no program of structural change will ever eliminate all social evils. Thus, More suggests, social reform should be tactical and limited rather than sweeping and structural. He advocates focusing on small adjustments that can alleviate social problems rather than seeking to totally eliminate them.

The questions that reflect this broad theme are very clearly posed in Book 1. This theme is less explicit in Book 2, which is comprised almost entirely of Raphael’s description of the Utopian way of life. Still, philosophical speculations about the origin of social problems and their solutions remain in the background. Read in light of these themes, the description of Utopia—which Raphael repeatedly praises as the most perfect or ideal form of society—can be understood as an application of Raphael’s own radical, structural approach to social problems.

The Relationship Between Individual Freedoms and the Common Good

Among the many social dynamics More explores in Utopia, the relationship between the freedoms of individual persons and the common good of the entire community is central. It is somewhat typical—especially in liberal, capitalist societies—to think about these concepts as opposed values. In this view, individual freedom is defined as one’s ability to make personal choices without being constrained by political, legal, or social forces. Where pursuit of the common good constrains one’s choices, the former is perceived as an impediment to individual freedom. Because of this, members of liberal-capitalist societies tend to think of individual freedoms and common goods as if they are locked in a tug-of-war: Where we seek to enhance one, we are liable to diminish the other.

According to Raphael, Utopia’s communist society presents a rather different vision of freedom and its relationship to the common good. Utopian society has attained a more authentic expression of individual freedom, he claims, because it realizes freedom through the pursuit of the common good rather than in opposition to it.

Raphael insists upon this despite the limitations the Utopian state imposes on individual choice. In Utopia is no question of trying to build a house that suits one’s personal taste or of selecting different clothes based on one’s mood. All these are standardized and provided by the state (53, 59). One cannot simply decide to take a holiday trip without permission from the local authorities (64-65). Nor is it possible to follow an individual desire to amass property, since there is no private property in Utopia. Such limitations on personal choice are pursued for the sake of the common good. They allow Utopians to organize an efficient economy based on use value rather than profit. In so doing, Utopia has eliminated almost all forms of need.

In his concluding remarks, in which he sings Utopia’s praises, Raphael insists that Utopians are not burdened by this form of life. Instead, they are truly free: free from poverty and hunger, free from political instability, free from servitude to the rich, and free from worry about the future of their children (110).

Given the liberal-capitalist theory of freedom as an expression of personal choice, Raphael’s insistence that the Utopians are freer than people living in capitalist countries is apt to seem strange. But Raphael is assuming a very different view of freedom. For Raphael, the basis of freedom is not freedom “for” undertaking some form of individual choice but freedom “from” pernicious, dehumanizing conditions.

The Pernicious Effects of Private Property

According to Raphael, problems such as political corruption, poverty, and crime are all perpetuated by the existence of private property. To minimize or eliminate these problems, it is necessary to rid society of private property and the illusory freedom and happiness that is often ascribed to it. In keeping with his views on the nature of freedom and justice, Raphael claims in Book 1 that justice cannot be achieved until private property is abolished completely (44-45).

Raphael’s insistence that private property must be abolished comes toward the end of Book 1. Given its placement, the claim plays an important role in the text’s thematic structure. First, it offers a summation of the previous discourse on the origin of social problems like crime and poverty and political challenges like corruption. Secondly, it constitutes a clear transition from the wide-ranging dialogues in Book 1 to Raphael’s extended description of Utopia in Book 2.

Gilles and More insist that Raphael’s political wisdom, gained through his world travels, would make him a valuable advisor to royal courts (19-20). Raphael rejects this idea, since he claims that kings have more interest in acquiring wealth and waging war than ruling justly (20). Read in light of Raphael’s call for the abolition of private property, the reason for such corrupt leadership becomes clear. As long as private property exists, it will remain the driving force in political life, and kings will rule in the interest of property and profit rather than people. Their advisors, keen to remain in power themselves, will be only too happy to support them in these endeavors. According to Raphael, this leads to the waging of unnecessary wars, misuse of the legal system to fill the royal coffers, and other abuses.

Raphael interprets broader social problems in terms of the pernicious effects of private property as well. Poverty is not a choice or a natural condition. No one would decide to be poor, and nature provides more than enough for all people to live in health and comfort. Poverty is perpetuated by the pursuit of private property whereby the few are enriched at the expense of the many (23). England serves as Raphael’s (and thus More’s) prime example. Motivated by a desire to profit from the demand for wool, the emerging merchant class seized up any agricultural land it could get its hands on, displacing the farmers who once grew crops there. In addition to causing instability in the wool market, this led to food shortages, inflation, and massive increases in unemployment and indigence (25-26). The predictable result of these trends were other social problems like begging and theft. Raphael notes that he sees the communist ideal as more compatible with Christianity than private property (99). In this, we find a clear distinction between the position More articulates and the materialist and atheistic critiques of private property advanced by Marxists in the 19th and 20th centuries. For Marx, communism meant the abolition of forms of social and economic alienation that gave rise to religion as a form of comforting fantasy used by the ruling class to stave off demands for social change. For Raphael, it seems, genuine religion is compatible with calls for justice and social change, and demands both.

Raphael’s call for the abolition of private property also serves as a pivot point between the two major sections of the work. After Raphael insists that social problems could be solved once and for all through the elimination of private property, More replies with several familiar criticisms. First, he insists that without the acquisition and enlargement of private property as a motivation, people would become lazy, living off the labor of others. As a result, there would be massive shortages of goods. This, in turn, would encourage violent crime, disorder, and a total lack of respect for authority (45).

Here we see two sides of the debate emerge in stark contrast: those who believe that private property is the source of all social ills and must be eliminated, and those who believe that communism would perpetuate the problems it seeks to solve. Raphael asserts that if More had seen Utopia’s prosperous, well-organized society, then he would see that his objections are misplaced (46).

More’s presentation of this theme clarifies his authorial choice to divide most of the novel into two large books. Raphael’s detailed description of Utopia in Book 2 constitutes a response to criticisms of the communist ideal offered by the character Thomas More in Book 1. This structure, which hinges on the theme of private property, invites the reader to recall the questions and debates raised in the first book while reading through Raphael’s account of Utopia in the second book.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
Unlock IconUnlock all 58 pages of this Study Guide

Plus, gain access to 8,800+ more expert-written Study Guides.

Including features:

+ Mobile App
+ Printable PDF
+ Literary AI Tools